Thursday 10 February 2022

Dei Viā Regiā: The Westminster Divine Anthony Tuckney On The Necessity Of Works For Salvation

By Ryan M. Hurd

[Ryan M. Hurd is an author and editor with a particular interest in systematics. He also translates Latin theological works mainly from the early modern period. He lives in Grand Rapids, MI.]

ABSTRACT

The question of the necessity of good works has deep bearing on soteriology, whether the explanation is held to distinguish from Roman Catholic teaching or the teaching of, for example, Antinomians. In his Praelectiones theologicae, Anthony Tuckney—an important Westminster divine—presents a careful articulation of one way of explaining the necessity of good works that sits well within the Reformed tradition. By this account, Tuckney argues that good works are necessary as the royal way walked to God.

-------------

Anthony Tuckney wrote, “[Good works] have the relation of order, such as a means have to an end, an antecedent to a consequent, a cause sine qua non to its effect, but they are not the cause properly efficient of salvation, either keeping it, as some want, much less effecting it either physically or morally—i.e., acquiring it meritoriously.”[1] Thus Tuckney summarizes his answer as to whether works are necessary for salvation.

It seems appropriate to give away the end at the beginning, for Tuckney’s discussion of the question is tight, complex, and perhaps pedantic. Indeed, Letham has called it a “sophisticated discussion”—accurate, if not understated.[2] Nevertheless, Tuckney’s discussion is a fine, careful treatment of the issue, one which, unfortunately, to this point has received no attention. Further, his larger work in which the question occurs, his Praelectiones theologicae, has likewise received very little treatment, perhaps because it is yet untranslated. The purpose of the present work is to trace and elucidate Tuckney’s argument therein regarding the necessity of good works. As a Westminster Divine heavily involved in drafting the Standards, Tuckney contributes an expanded perspective on the debates of the Assembly and its work. While the Standards themselves will not be considered here, this article should lay the groundwork to expand current Reformed discussion on the necessity of good works, specifically for those wishing to remain confessionally bound by the authors’ intentions in the Standards.

We will begin with a brief overview of Tuckney and his work at Westminster. Then, we will proceed through the status controversiae, distinctiones, and solutiones, and finally conclude.

I. Overview Of Tuckney And His Work At Westminster

Anthony Tuckney (1599–1670) was born in Kirton, Lincolnshire.[3] He trained and then later taught at Emmanuel College, Cambridge, beginning in 1619. He received a Bachelor of Arts in 1617, a Master of Arts in 1620, and a Bachelor of Divinity in 1627. He became vicar of St. Botolph’s Church in Boston, Lincolnshire, in 1633, succeeding John Cotton when he emigrated to the Massachusetts Bay Colony. In 1643 Tuckney was called to labor at the Westminster Assembly, which he served until 1648.

Tuckney’s work at the Assembly has been acknowledged in brief[4] but largely overlooked, especially with regards to the extent he impacted the Standards. On August 30, 1643, he delivered a sermon before Commons. Though he did not often speak at the Assembly itself (only ten times at plenary sessions),[5] the extent of his work is not thus to be disparaged. When the Assembly revised the Thirty-Nine Articles, Tuckney belonged to the first and what some have argued was the most influential committee.[6]

During the subsequent work on the Standards, Tuckney was involved in numerous other committees as well, discussing a variety of topics.[7] He was appointed on December 2, 1644, to the committee for drafting a catechism, and had significant impact.[8] He later chaired the committee for the Larger Catechism, and also replaced Palmer as chairman of the Shorter Catechism in September 1646.[9] Beyond this, his primary activity, which was also the most significant for the Standards themselves, was in “wording and methodizing” the Standards, as part of the committee that did so.[10] Thus, as Van Dixhoorn notes, Tuckney became a “key figure behind the doctrinal texts of the Assembly.”[11]

In fact, according to Cho’s analysis, Tuckney “played a leading role in drafting and reporting the articles that correspond to a total of twelve chapters of the Confession.”[12] He reported on numerous articles: “Free Will,” “Perseverance and Certainty of Salvation,” “Sanctification and Saving Faith,” “Repentance unto Life,” “Good Works,” and “Religious Worship and Sabbath Day.”[13] As Cho points out, these make up the majority of the soteriological sections of the Confession.[14] While, as others have noted, no individual should tower too far above the others in what are undoubtedly “compromise documents,”[15] it nevertheless is clear that Tuckney had significant impact.

He resumed his teaching at Emmanuel in April 1645, though, by request of the Assembly, he continued to labor and be present with the Divines and their work.[16] He was later appointed Regius Professor of Divinity in 1655 and remained in that capacity until 1661, when he withdrew, largely because of the Restoration, which made many Puritans’ lives difficult. He died in London in February 1670.

Tuckney’s works consist mostly of letters, sermons, and a catechism.[17] Additionally, his most doctrinal treatise by far is his Praelectiones theologicae. The work contains a number of questions related mostly to christological and soteriological issues, and also, for our purposes, contains the question on the necessity of good works.

II. Status Controversiae

The question that concerns us here is Question 32 of the Praelectiones, which asks whether good works are necessary for salvation.[18] The context of the question, and the controversy surrounding it, is specifically contra Antinomos & Libertinos—against the Antinomians and Libertines—who argued that good works were not at all necessary for salvation.[19]

While these groups were specifically his object of dispute, Tuckney locates the question also against the Catholics, whose position he denies without equivocation from the outset. In fact, throughout his treatment Tuckney reveals his concern that, while dealing with the Antinomians, the Catholics must also be refuted. It is likely for this reason that his primary sparring partner throughout the work is no named Antinomian, but rather the Cardinal Bellarmine himself, standing in as the embodiment of the sophistica Pontificiorum.

In addition to these groups Tuckney also bears in mind the Lutherans. He notes initially the reality of a debate among them in a prior generation, among the two groups of the Majoristas and Flacianos. Despite the reality of this debate, Tuckney concludes that it was only a λογομαχιαν (or war over words), as in his opinion both groups’ feelings on the issue were unanimous (with the Reformed).

Therefore, Tuckney in his explanation wants to (1) uncover the Catholic “sophistry,” lest in affirming necessity against the Antinomians any would be deceived; (2) remove ambiguity in the question, especially regarding those in the Lutheran camp (and some Reformed) who have lack of clarity on the point; and (3) provide a resolution to the controversy. To this end he moves to a number of distinctions.

III. Distinctiones

His distinctions are among four different categories: good works, salvation, necessity, and the persons with regards to whom the necessity is considered. These distinctions Tuckney will use later in his discussion, but we will survey them briefly here.

First, regarding good works, there are broadly two types: external and internal. The former are things that are “said or done,” deeds and words; the latter are the internal habits of the saints. He describes the latter as consisting in the “operations of the mind, will, and affections” which flow from the internal habits.[20]

Second, regarding salvation, Tuckney distinguishes between salvation more commonly taken as specifically the “height of the heavenly glory,” or the “whole of grace until glory.”[21] The latter one, Tuckney asserts from Matt 1:21, can also include “first justification”—declarative or initial justification—in se.

Third, regarding necessity, Tuckney delineates five major types. He notes that though there are many sorts of necessity, he will only treat those which specifically relate to the current issue:

  1. The necessity either of coaction, which “forces someone reluctant to act,” or of obligation, “such as an action possessed without freedom.”[22] The former refers to strict compulsion either against or contrary to the will of another; the latter does not include such violation.
  2. The necessity of precept, or of a means.[23] The necessity of precept is “that which God commands for the purpose of achieving some end by any way.”[24] He cites 1 Cor 9:16 as an example, where Paul speaks of a necessity laid upon him to preach the gospel. It is important to note that in the context of that passage, Paul argues that this is a stewardship he does not do of his own will (which therefore would include a reward). The necessity of a means is, as the name denotes, that “without which it is altogether not granted to accomplish that end.”[25] Here Tuckney cites Acts 14:22: “through many tribulations we must enter the kingdom.”
  3. An antecedent, consequent, or concomitant necessity.[26] More of these later.
  4. The necessity of presence alone, or an efficient necessity.[27] The former is “that by which something is necessary to be present to a thing which we achieve”; the latter actually “communicates necessary efficiency to the acquisition of a thing.”[28]
  5. Finally, regarding efficient necessity, there are broadly two ways this could be understood. First, of a “cause sine qua non of a disposition, aptitude of a subject, of a condition, of a means, of something attending, and of a way for the purpose of accomplishing something.”[29] This, Tuckney notes, is broadly (but improperly) called causality, a cause sine qua non. Second, efficient necessity taken “strictly and properly” is truly understood as an efficient cause in se, which “either physically produces or effects something … ex merito puts a thing into existence.”[30]

The fourth and final main category of distinctions is regarding the persons “for whose salvation good works must be judged necessary to exist or not.”[31] Here Tuckney distinguishes between infantes and those who have become adultos. Regarding the former category, it is not clear whether he means specifically newborns properly so called, or figuratively—that is, newborn babes in Christ. This will be handled directly below, although here it should be noted that Tuckney includes with the description of infantes those who “are immediately after regeneration encountering death,”[32] and therefore it would seem initially that he is using the term figuratively. Furthermore, note Tuckney’s contrasting definition of adultos, or, those who are mature. They are those who have “obtained their use of reason and have become mature, who also after the commencement of new life for a while completely enjoy the use of light and have sufficient opportunities for acting well.”[33]

IV. Solutiones

Before Tuckney turns to employing these distinctions, he spends quite some time locating the issue in the context of theological debate, primarily against the Catholics (via Bellarmine). While we do not want to get too occupied with this question, it is nevertheless important to note it in brief.

1. Some Brief Background

Tuckney is aware of those attempting to unite “us, truly of the Reformed, either of Luther or Calvin” to the Antinomians and Libertines in order to overturn the whole.[34] Chief of such culprits he cites as Bellarmine, who argued that the Reformed “suppose that it is possible for man to be saved, even if he does no good works.”[35] Bellarmine and other Catholics argued that the Reformed wanted “to hold that good works have no judgment about salvation,”[36] and that the Reformed and the Antinomians so well known in England at the time were one and the same.

Against this accusation, Tuckney intends to be very clear and extricate the Reformed from such a charge. However, the issue is further complicated when some Reformed are “marveling at the phrase ‘they are necessary for salvation.’ Some of the Lutherans hesitated, and even now are hesitating”[37]—and that despite the fact that “our writers and teachers seriously, zealously, and continuously teach, urge, command, and impress the necessity of things that have been commanded, owed, ordered, and overturn these hypotheses.”[38] Therefore, against the accusations of the Catholics, the errors of the Antinomians, and the confusion of some Lutherans, Tuckney begins to establish in what sense good works are necessary for salvation.

2. The Persons And Works

He begins with the last category of distinctions first: regarding the persons. Here Tuckney clearly asserts that it is only those adultos of which we understand, or “at least those who have obtained use of reason.”[39]

To this though he adds also a secondary qualification for the persons being considered, namely, that they “after the first point of regeneration are living long enough that they may have the time and occasion for working well.”[40] This becomes an important distinction, yielding two separate groups within the category of adultos, or, those who have the use of reason: (1) those who have opportunity for good works, and (2) those who do not. (It is to be noted that Tuckney is a bit hazy about applying this distinction distinctly throughout the section.)

It is with the above distinctions in mind that we turn again to the question introduced earlier, namely, what is meant by infantes and adultos? Does either of these terms carry only a physical or spiritual idea, or perhaps both? It appears that Tuckney has only the physical in view, though there is some ambiguity. For example, the way Tuckney handles this point can be seen in brief in his None But Christ, where he treats the salvation of infants and means specifically those who are physically young. He also includes with this category those who are “deaf and blind from the womb; and so without this possibility of having Christ so revealed to them, as for them by faith to lay hold on him.”[41] The reason why such can be saved is based upon their relationship to the covenant of grace. They are “so wrapt up in it, as also to be wrapt up in the bundle of life.”[42]

However, Tuckney extends this category to also include a different group of people who are physically mature, whereby he indicates that he does not intend strictly to limit the question to physical infants. He writes that God “acteth in the souls of Believers in articulo mortis [at the point of death, e.g., a death-bed conversion], when some of them are as little able to put forth an act of reason, as they were in articulo nativitatis [at the point of birth].”[43] There is a relationship then between the infant category (which has already been noted as including those physically handicapped) and those who are physically adults.

Regarding how such are saved, Tuckney writes, with regards to infants, that they do not have “actual faith, so as to exert it,” yet they may have the infused habit of it.[44] Here the habitus idea is present, which in his Praelectiones Tuckney will turn to in order that he may clarify the question. But here, he includes with the habitus the idea of sanctification—faith working in love, or faith with external works—wherein he turns immediately to deal in this context with what he terms the “pleonasme of love” in 1 Tim 1:14, in which could be a possible objection that it is both faith “and love” as “the way … they might be saved.”[45]

However, as Tuckney describes it, this is not just a “pleonasme of love,” but rather “a hyper-pleonasme of love.”[46] It is a “Pleonasme of a sparkling wit and pen,” but “no solid Divinity.”[47] Thus it is not faith working externally in love that is necessary for salvation in this case, but rather only the internal habit.

From this place it appears that Tuckney works with the category of physical infants, yet has some degree of relationship with those who have death-bed conversions and are thus spiritually immature. Regarding both, the works considered is the infused habit of works.

And this is consistent with, secondly, how Tuckney continues in his Praelectiones. After introducing the distinction of persons, he brings in Bellarmine, Aquinas, and Alphonsus on the question, who (as Catholics!) taught that “infants and also adults recently baptized” are saved even if “immediately they depart from this life.”[48] Granting that they “did not have the time and opportunity for working”—again, an important factor—“his faith without works is sufficient for him, and it is counted unto righteousness.”[49] As Tuckney explains, the reason this is true is because they are “counted to fulfill the whole law, who after justification have not violated it, and who bear charity, which is the fullness of the law, at least habitually in their heart.”[50]

Nevertheless, Tuckney notes that some Reformed theologians are not happy with this explanation, citing Chamier, referencing his De operum necessitate.[51] Therefore, to continue to unravel the issue and propose a satisfactory solution, Tuckney proceeds with his distinctions to solve the issue.

He moves to the distinction regarding good works, either external or internal. He notes that Bellarmine, standing in for Catholics en masse, wants the question to deal primarily with “the infused habit of grace of the saints,” with reference specifically to initial justification.[52]

Having granted this point, Tuckney further elucidates external works, quoting from Rom 10:10 that not only by the heart it is believed for righteousness, but also with the mouth confession is made. He affirms that such are also necessary for salvation, with this qualification: “provided that one is granted time and opportunity for working.”[53]

Here then he weaves back in the “infants and adults without time to work” relationship. With regards to internal good works, he concedes they are likewise necessary. They cannot be “completely absent.” Furthermore, they ought “necessarily to be present in all having the use of reason,” even if they are “immediately after regeneration taken away by death.”[54] Those who are physically mature who come to faith must have internal good works, though “faith without external works is sufficient for him, and it is counted unto righteousness”[55]—because he has the infused habit of grace.

Further with reference to internal good works, with respect to infants, Tuckney notes they are also necessary for them likewise, though this is considered to be only the “root of the thing,” the “seed of God,” or, as Bellarmine terms it, “the infused habit of grace.”[56] How this is to be distinguished from the “full-flower” infused habit of works is not made clear.

To summarize Tuckney’s point, there are two categories of persons of which he is speaking. First, with respect to infants (and presumably those mentally handicapped, i.e., not possessing the ability to reason properly), he affirms that, as the “seed of God” or the “root of the thing,” internal works are necessary for salvation. Second, with regards to adults, or those having the use of reason, there are two main categories: those who have opportunity, and those who do not. If the latter is in view, only the internal good works are necessary; if the former, then to such must be added external works as well. As Tuckney says, “Thus, up till now—namely, in these various ways of understanding—good works are necessary to all for salvation.”[57]

So far, so good, Tuckney affirms. However, as he has previously pointed out, necessity can be spoken of in many ways, and therefore the previously made distinctions regarding necessity should be brought forward for further clarity. And note well, though Tuckney does not say so explicitly, it appears that moving forward he will be dealing with this category throughout the remainder of his distinctions: the necessity of external good works with respect to adult persons having reason.

3. Necessity And Salvation

(I) Necessity Of Compulsion, Or Obligation?

Tuckney first deals with the necessity of coaction or compulsion, which he flatly denies against Bellarmine. Here he refers to that necessity for salvation “we have made complete by the fact of our performing or neglecting.”[58] He opts rather for the necessity of obligation—affirming that we indeed should be willing, but not “therefore free” (here, voluntary not being “opposed to obligation, but to forced and slavelike”[59]). Indeed, the necessity is obligatory with respect to us.

To this he adds the necessity of precept, which is the basis of the necessity of obligation. Regarding the former, this is very clearly taught in Scripture, Tuckney citing Matt 5:16 and Titus 3:8, 14. Regarding the latter, he cites Mal 1:6 and Luke 17:10: “As long as we remain creatures of God, and redeemed by the blood of the Lord Christ,” it is a debt which can never be “settled.”[60]

But can we say anything further? It appears so. Having established that there is both a necessity of precept (which Tuckney uses as a catch-all for necessity of obligation as well—it is together “both obligated and ordered”), Tuckney turns to discuss whether this necessity is (and, if so, how it is) a means to salvation specifically.[61] But before answering the question directly, he pulls in the prior distinctions regarding salvation, which he expands and clarifies.

(II) Initial Salvation, Or Future?

With regards to a necessity of means for salvation, such a salvation should be considered in different ways, of which three are possible: “having been begun, or in progress, or in the end and final completion.”[62] Only the first and last of these concern him here.

The first refers to the initial calling, justification, and adoption.[63] Here, for the sake of argument only against the Catholics, Tuckney takes up the question of necessity with respect to this understanding of salvation. If the necessity should be considered with respect to salvation viewed in this way—specifically, good works considered to be necessary in an antecedent necessity—“we would deny this entirely.” Tuckney cross-references Augustine, and moves forward: “Good works do not precede being justified, but nevertheless they follow justification.”[64]

Nevertheless, they are indeed to be considered with respect to this understanding of salvation as necessary consequently and “also by that in a sense concomitantly.” Tuckney affirms they are in that way necessary, based off the connection between justification and sanctification.[65] He writes: “If sanctification should come (as it ought to be used) into the judgment of this salvation which has been attained, then good works, if by the signification of them they include the internal habit of grace, would concern the formal nature of this salvation, and thus from it could never be separated. If they should denote its operations, they would be likewise inseparably necessary to this divine nature, and have been effected by this particular cause.”[66] Note the idea here is for proving or validating the reality of initial justification.

(III) Necessity With Respect To Future Salvation.

Tuckney, having dispatched with salvation considered in the first sense, now turns to what appears to be his primary object: “We believe [good works] are necessary for acquiring salvation at the future time.”[67] There is both a necessity for the presence of good works, as well as an antecedent necessity for salvation at the last day. Tuckney cites with regards to the former Heb 12:14 and Rev 21:27; and the latter, Matt 5:8.

But here Tuckney introduces an objection: “But there is not also causal and efficient necessity, is there?”[68] By introducing this question with the num particle, he tips his hand—no, there is not. Nevertheless, he handles the objection, noting first that the question is understood in various ways. It could be understood as delineating a necessity as “whatever power, by a tendency or affection, which in some of the thing is present for the purpose of achieving another thing, or even approaching it.”[69] Tuckney notes that some of the Reformed have affirmed this, such as Zanchi: “We do not deny absolutely that good works are the cause of salvation—namely, the instrumental, rather than the efficient, and as a cause which they call sine qua non.”[70]

Even beyond Zanchi (who is admittedly a bit ambiguous here), Tuckney notes that Piscator himself has said there is an efficient causality on the basis of Eph 1:4. Johann Piscator, a contemporary of Tuckney who addressed the question of the necessity of good works, was well known to the Assembly for his work on the active obedience of Christ (which affects this question, and which Piscator handles in the context of Christian obedience), which was part of the debate of the Divines. And, while not specifically citing a place in Piscator, Tuckney most likely means his Analysis logica sex epistolarum Pauli. To provide context for Tuckney’s answer, Piscator needs to be briefly considered.

In his Analysis, Piscator lays out the first fourteen verses of Ephesians as relaying the causes of salvation. Underneath the heading of the efficient cause of salvation, specifically the actions of God the Father, Piscator notes that “he has sanctified us unto a blameless life.”[71] Furthermore, regarding v. 4, he writes: “But [Paul] adds the final cause of election, which concerns partly us, and partly God—namely, that we may live holily. For this pertains both for the purpose of renewing our nature and for glorifying the name of God. But this is our sanctification itself: it is an action of God, by which we among others are led to salvation. And thus it has the idea of some efficient cause.”[72]

It is probably specifically this last phrase that Tuckney is referencing. Piscator will argue extensively from this later. He lays out those whom he has in view further in his work: “Because we have been elected unto this end, that we may be sanctified and blameless before the face of God, therefore they argue wrongly who teach, ‘If I have been elected, I will be saved. Whatever I will have done, or however I will have lived. Therefore, it is permitted to securely indulge in the desires of the flesh.’ On the contrary, if you are elect, God will give to you grace that you may live holily, and that you may reach by the way of holiness (the way, I say, not meritoriously) to eternal life, to which you have been elected.”[73] He is thus careful to note that “because God has elected us unto eternal life in Christ before the foundation of the world, the consequence is that no one by his actions is promised by God that he is elected.”[74]

To answer Piscator’s “idea of some efficient cause,” Tuckney asserts three things to confirm that the answer truly is, no. First, he considers the matter with regards to qualifications required in the persons being saved “and so habits of the subject for achieving salvation.” In that respect, they are necessary. However, these are “qualities of the ones being saved, not properly of salvation”[75]—and therefore cannot be efficient causes for salvation.

Second, considering works as conditions for achieving salvation,[76] Tuckney points out that it is only in the sense as “without which salvation is not gained,” not as “effective conditions, from whose proper efficiency salvation is acquired.”[77] That is to say, conditions here (as in contracts) can be of two types—“antecedent, which grant a cause for the contract, and constitute its foundation and essence; or consequent, which are added to the preceding, which do not constitute the essence of the contract nor change it, although they are nevertheless obligatory to one of the two parties.”[78]

The introduction of covenant terminology here includes the pactum salutis. (While he does not here outline anything further on the pactum salutis, it is here to be remembered that he is dealing with future justification—so this is not surprising.) Tuckney notes that good works do not constitute that covenant with respect to its basis, but rather the conditions here are of the second kind. The first respect would be an efficient cause in se of the contract. The second respect yields an interesting problem. Good works, though their presence does not “constitute the pactum salutis,” nevertheless are those “whose nature and power it is that, although the presence of them does not effect salvation, nevertheless the absence can hinder it.”[79]

Tuckney appears to be equivocating slightly. He never names this cause, but rather provides an illustration—that of temperance and wisdom. Temperance does not create wisdom; however, “its absence impedes” it.[80] He concludes thus: “Because saving faith always and necessarily has been surrounded by holiness and good works, from the absence of those conditions altogether faith is understood to be necessarily absent. Hence, there can be no salvation, but certain perdition.”[81] Clearly, however, whatever this type of cause is, it cannot be considered properly an efficient cause.

Third, the implication is that good works are simply “means attending salvation ... which have no affect at all for salvation.”[82] The means here are thus instrumental. Here, Tuckney returns to remove any calumny regarding Zanchi: “Zanchi wants that instrumental cause not of salvation itself through its efficiency”—(though admittedly, to this author, this idea is a bit abstract).[83] Again though Tuckney turns illustrative, quoting approvingly from Bernard, “They are the way to the kingdom, but not the cause of reigning”;[84] or, again interpreting Zanchi, the “wedding garment for approaching” the marriage of the Lamb, rather than the “accomplishing of the wedding itself.”[85]

“In summary,” Tuckney concludes, “[good works] have the relation of order, such as a means have to an end, an antecedent to a consequent, a cause sine qua non to its effect, but they are not the cause properly efficient of salvation, either keeping it, as some want, much less effecting it either physically or morally—i.e., acquiring it meritoriously.”[86]

V. Conclusion

Tuckney will continue and return to dealing with the Catholics, and then the Lutherans, and then the Antinomians, and others. Having distanced himself from the Antinomians, his main desire in the last section appears to warn about going too far back into the Catholics: “Let us beware, in order that, while we are all thus rising up against the Antinomians, we would not seem to move gradually over to the camp of the Catholics, or at least seem to be favorable to them.”[87] We will not proceed further down this route, but simply summarize what has gone before, where Tuckney has established his nuanced position.

It probably is best first to provide a rough sketch of what has preceded (see Figure 1). We established that Tuckney with respect to infants holds to the necessity only of internal good works. The same also applies for adults who are regenerate and then immediately die—though the difference between the two is the former is a “seed” and the latter the “full-bloom” of internal good works. With regards to adults—namely, those who have reasoning capacities—both internal and external good works are necessary for salvation.

With regards to the type of necessity, we noted that, against the Catholics, there was no necessity of coaction, but was one of obligation or of precept. This, however, can be said of all creatures—devils and angels included—and therefore is not especially helpful in the discussion. Whether there is a necessity as a means to salvation is answered affirmatively, with qualifications. If salvation is considered as initial salvation, then the necessity is not antecedent but consequent or concomitant in the sense that good works prove or validate the reality of salvation. If salvation is considered as future or final, then good works are necessary both by a necessity of their presence, or, existence, as well as being antecedent to the attainment of eternal life. This is not—contra-Piscator—an efficient necessity properly so called, but is truly a cause sine qua non, the absence of which (hypothetical) would prove to undermine the possibility of salvation. In this way it is perhaps most correct to describe such as an instrumental cause. Thus, according to Tuckney, with respect to those who have use of their reason, who have time and opportunity for good works, both internal and external good works are necessary for final salvation with regards to their presence as an antecedent, instrumental cause sine qua non. Or, as we could summarize for him: Are good works necessary for salvation? Yes, but we distinguish.

Figure 1. A chart showing Anthony Tuckney's nuanced position on salvation and works.

Notes

  1. Anthony Tuckney, Praelectiones theologicae (Amsterdam: Printed by Stephani Swart for Jonathan Robinson and George Wells, 1679), 233–34.
  2. Robert Letham, The Westminster Assembly: Reading Its Theology in Historical Context (Philipsburg, NJ: Presbyterian & Reformed, 2009), 282.
  3. For further biographical information, see Thomas Baker, History of the College of St. John the Evangelist, Cambridge, 2 vols. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1869), 1:229–32; William Barker, Puritan Profiles (Fearn, Ross-Shire: Mentor, 1999), 175–79; Edmund Calamy, The Nonconformist’s Memorial: Being an Account of the Ministers, who were ejected or silenced after the Restoration, particularly by the Act of Uniformity, which took place on Bartholomew-day, Aug. 24, 1662 (London: Printed for W. Harris, 1775), 1:205–8; Patrick Collinson, “Tuckney, Anthony,” Oxford Dictionary of National Biography, ed. H. C. G. Matthew and Brian Harrison (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), 55:504–6; Alexander Gordon, “Tuckney, Anthony,” Dictionary of National Biography, ed. Sidney Lee (London: Macmillan, 1899), 57:286–88; James Reid, Memoirs of the Lives and Writings of Those Eminent Divines, Who Convened in the Famous Assembly at Westminster, in the Seventeenth Century (Paisley: Stephen and Andrew Young, 1811), 1:186–89. For the most comprehensive introduction to his life, see Youngchun Cho, “Union with Christ in the Theology of Anthony Tuckney (1599–1670)” (PhD diss., Westminster Theological Seminary, 2015), 9–52. Cho’s dissertation is the only one to date on Tuckney, and I am indebted to him also for pointing out the sources in this note.
  4. See, for instance, Barker, Puritan Profiles, 175–79; John Bower, The Larger Catechism: A Critical Text and Introduction (Grand Rapids: Reformation Heritage, 2010), 17–18; John H. Leith, Assembly at Westminster: Reformed Theology in the Making (Richmond: John Knox, 1973), 46–47; Letham, Westminster Assembly.
  5. Chad Van Dixhoorn, The Minutes and Papers of the Westminster Assembly, 1643–1653, 5 vols. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012), 2:52, 166, 180, 230, 360, 3:131, 278, 298, 372, 377.
  6. Baker, History of the College of St. John the Evangelist, 2:644.
  7. See Cho, “Union with Christ,” 36–37, for a summary of these topics.
  8. Bower, Larger Catechism, 6.
  9. Van Dixhoorn, Minutes and Papers, 4:697.
  10. Bower, Larger Catechism, 18.
  11. Van Dixhoorn, Minutes and Papers, 3:596–97.
  12. Cho, “Union with Christ,” 39. The chapters of the Confession are 9, 13, 14, 15, 16, 17, 18, 19, 21, 22, 23, and 24.
  13. See Van Dixhoorn, Minutes and Papers, 4:181, 276, 284, 315, 589, 599.
  14. Cho, “Union with Christ,” 2.
  15. Letham, Westminster Assembly, 111.
  16. Van Dixhoorn, Minutes and Papers, 4:697.
  17. They are as follows: “A Briefe & Pithy Catechism as It Was Delivered in Emmanuell Colledge Chapel 1628 per Anthony Tuckney” (MS. 3.1.13 in the Emmanuel College Library Special Collections, Cambridge University); The Balme of Gilead, for the Wounds of England Applyed in a Sermon Preached at Westminster Before the Honourable House of Commons, at the Late Solemne Fast, August 30, 1643 (London: Printed by Richard Bishop for Samuel Gellibrand…, 1643); None but Christ, or a Sermon Upon Acts 4.12. Preached at St. Maries in Cambridge … July 4, 1652. To Which Is Annexed, an Enquiry After What Hope May Be Had of the Salvation of 1. Heathens. 2. Those of the Old World, the Jews and Others Before Christ. 3. Such as Die Infants, and Idiots, &c. Now Under the Gospel. By Anthony Tuckney (London: Printed for John Rothwell and S. Gellibrand, 1654); Thanatoktasia, or, Death Disarmed: And the Grave Swallowed up in Victory. A Sermon … at S. Maries in Cambridge, Decemb. 22. 1653. at the Publick Funerals of Dr. Hill … With a Short Account of His Life and Death. To Which Are Added Two Sermons More Upon the Same Text … By Anthony Tuckney (London: Printed for J. Rothwel and S. Gellibrand, 1654); introduction to A Brief Exposition with Practical Observations upon the Whole Book of Canticles, by John Cotton (London: Printed by T. R. & E. M. for Ralph Smith, 1655); A Good Day Well Improved, or Five Sermons Upon Acts 9.31 Two of Which Were Preached at Pauls, and Ordered to Be Printed. To Which Is Annexed a Sermon on 2 Tim. 1.13. Preached at St. Maries in Cambridge, on the Commencement Sabbath, June 30. 1650. By Anthony Tuckney D. D. and Master of St. Johns College in Cambridge (n.p.: Printed by J. F. for S. Gellibrand, 1656); Forty sermons upon several occasions by the late reverend and learned Anthony Tuckney … sometimes master of Emmanuel and St. John’s Colledge (successively) and Regius professor of divinity in the University of Cambridge, published according to his own copies his son Jonathan Tuckney (London: Printed by J. M. for Jonathan Robinson and Brabazon Aylmer…, 1679); Praelectiones theologicae (1679); and Benjamin Whichcote, Eight Letters of Dr. Anthony Tuckney and Dr. Benjamin Whichcote Concerning the Use of Reason in Religion, the Differences of Opinion Among Christians, the Reconciliation of Sinners with God, the Studies and Learning of a Minister of the Gospel (London: Printed for J. Payne, 1753).
  18. “Bona opera sunt necessaria ad salutem” (Praelectiones, 228).
  19. “Contra Antinomos & Libertinos a D. Respondente instituitur hodierna Controversia; contra Antinomos, inquam qui tam Doctrina quam praxi bona opera ad salutem ita minime necessaria esse somniant, ut ei impedimento esse blasphemando asserant” (ibid.).
  20. “Bona opera sunt … interna, quae intellectus, voluntatis, affectuum operationibus consant” (ibid.).
  21. “Salutis vox saepius & vulgo totius rei … & caelestis gloriae fastigium magis proprie denotat: saepe etiam totam gratiae ad gloriam usque” (ibid.).
  22. “Necessitas vel coactionis, quae invitum cogit ad agendum, vel debiti, ut actio pro non arbitraria habeatur” (ibid., 229).
  23. “Necessitas praecepti, vel medii” (ibid.).
  24. “Necessitas praecepti … est, quod ad finem aliquem consequendum Deus quovis modo jubet” (ibid.).
  25. “[Necessitas medii est] sine quo finem illum assequi omnino non datur” (ibid.).
  26. “Aliquid alteri necessario annectitur, vel antecedenter, vel consequenter, vel concomitanter” (ibid.).
  27. “Necessitas ista potest esse vel solius praesentiae, vel simul etiam efficientiae” (ibid.).
  28. “Illa, qua aliquid rei quam assequimur adesse necesse est … haec illius est quod necessariam efficaciam impertit ad ipsam rei acquisitionem” (ibid.).
  29. “Est causae sine qua non, dispositionis & habilitatis subjecti, conditionis, medii, administrantis, & viae ad rem assequendam” (ibid.).
  30. “Phyisce producit & efficit … ex merito suo rem in esse ponit” (ibid.).
  31. “Ad quarum salutem bona opera, necessaria esse vel non esse censenda sunt” (ibid.).
  32. “Infantes … & statim post regenerationem mortem oppetentes” (ibid.).
  33. “Ii qui rationis usum adepti & adultiores facti sunt, qui etiam post novae vitae exordia aliquandiu lucis usura perfruuntur, & bene operandi idoneas opportunitates habent” (ibid.).
  34. “Haec Antinomos & Libertinos … configant licet convitia, Nos, vere Reformatorum vel Lutheri vel Calvini sequacium, nullos feriunt” (ibid., 230).
  35. “Calumniatorem ergo, eumque mendacissimum agit Bellarminus, cum haec nobis assingit, quasi omnino existimemus, posse hominem salvari, etiam, si nulla opera bona faciat” (ibid.).
  36. “Nos tenere vult bona opera nullam revelationem habere ad salutem” (ibid.).
  37. “Ad Phrasin quidem istam necessaria esse ad salutem ambigebant, haesitabant Lutheranorum aliqui, atque etiamnum haesitant” (ibid.).
  38. “Hoc Scriptores & Concionatores nostri scrio, sedulo, incessanter docent, urgent, imperant, necessitatem mandati, debiti, ordinis, consequentiae, hypotheseos inculcant” (ibid., 229).
  39. “Saltem ratioinis usum adeptis” (ibid., 231).
  40. “& qui insuper post primam regenerationem tam diu vivunt, ut bene operandi tempus & occasionem habeant” (ibid.).
  41. Tuckney, None But Christ, 133.
  42. Ibid., 136. It is important to note that the context of this specific question is: granted that infants of believers may be saved having passed away early in life, does that not then include heathens who have not heard of Christ?
  43. Ibid., 135.
  44. Ibid., 136.
  45. Ibid., 138–39.
  46. Ibid.
  47. Ibid., 139.
  48. “Nam Bellarminus, qui adeo operum necessitatem urget, infantes excipit, atque adultos etiam recens batpizatos, quos salvari concedit, si continuo ex hac vita decedant” (Praelectiones, 231).
  49. “Ei vero who non operatur (si modo operandi tempus & oppurtunitatem non habuerit) fides eius sine operibus ei sufficit, & reputatur in justitiam” (ibid.).
  50. “Censentur totam legem implere, qui post justificationem eam non violaverunt, & qui charitatem, quae est Legis plenitudo saltem habitualiter in corde gerunt” (ibid.).
  51. See Daniel Chamier, Panstratiae Catholicae, sive controversiarum de religione adversus pontificios corpus, 4 vols. (Geneva, 1606), 3.15.1 and 3.
  52. “Interna reducendus est infusus gratiae sanctificantis habitus, in quo praecipue ipse Bellarminus justificationem consistere vult” (Praelectiones, 231).
  53. “Si modo concedatur operandi tempus & opportunitas” (ibid.).
  54. “Non omnino abesse concedimus, imo necessarie adesse debere affirmamus omnibus rationis usum habentibus, licet continuo post Regenerationem morte abreptis” (ibid.).
  55. “Fides eius sine operibus ei sufficit, & reputatur in justitiam” (ibid.).
  56. “Radicem rei … semen Dei … infusum gratiae habitum” (ibid.).
  57. “Adeoque huc usque, hoc vario scilicet intelligendi modo, bona opera omnibus ad salutem necessaria sunt” (ibid.).
  58. “Ut pro arbitrio nostro salva salute ea vel facto exequi, vel negligere nobis integrum sit” (ibid., 232).
  59. “Vox illa voluntaria non opponitur debitae, sed asperae & servili” (ibid.).
  60. “Quod quamdiu Dei Creaturae, Christi etiam Domini Sanguine redempti manemus, nunquam expungi queat” (ibid.).
  61. “An vero aeque ac necessitas praecepti & debiti & ordinis, etiam & medii ad salutem asserenda est?” (ibid.).
  62. “Initio, vel progressu, vel fine & perfectione ultima” (ibid.).
  63. “Salus … incipit a prima vocatione, justificatione, adoptione” (ibid.). Tuckney cites Rom 4:6 and Eph 2:6 as examples.
  64. “Bona opera non praecedunt justificandum, sed sequuntur tamen justificatum” (ibid.).
  65. “At consequenter (atque eo in sensu concomitanter) saluti in justificatione adeptae necessaria sunt” (ibid.).
  66. “Si Sanctificatio (uti debet) in huius adeptae salutis censum veniat, bona opera si internum gratiae habitum significatu suo comprehendant, de ipsa huius salutis formalitate sunt, adeoque ab ea separari nequeunt: si eius operationes denotent, Divinae huic naturae aeque inseparabiliter necessaria sunt, ac effecta causis suis propriis” (ibid.).
  67. “Sed ad salutem olim adipiscendam necessaria esse credimus” (ibid.).
  68. “Num vero & necessitate causalitatis & efficientia?” (ibid., 233).
  69. “Causalitas enim & efficientia large & improprie sumi potest pro qualibet vi, tendentia vel affectione, quae rei alicui inest ad rem aliam consequendam, vel etiam adeundam” (ibid.).
  70. “Non simpliciter negamus bona opera esse causam salutis nempe instrumentalem potius quam efficientem, & ut causam, quam vocant, sine qua non” (ibid.).
  71. “Sanctificavit nos ad vitam inculpatam” (Johann Piscator, Analysis logica sex epistolarum Pauli [1596], 101).
  72. “Addit autem electionis causam finalem, quae partim nos respicit, partim Deum; nempe ut sancte vivamus: hoc enim & ad naturam nostram instaurandum & ad nomen Dei glorificandum pertinet. Haec autem ipsa nostri sanctificatio, actio Dei est, qua nos inter alias ad salutem adducit: ac proinde rationem aliquam causae efficientis habet” (ibid., 88).
  73. “Quum electi simus in hunc finem, ut simus sancti & inculpati coram Deo: Ergo male argumentatur qui dicunt: Si sum electus, salvus fiam; quicquid egero, seu quomodocunque vixero: Ergo secure indulgere cupiditatibus carnis licet. Imo, Si es electus, Deus dabit tibi gratiam ut sancte vivas, & via sanctitatis (via, inquam, non merito) ad vitam aeternam, ad quam electus es, pervenias” (ibid., 103).
  74. “Quum Deus nos ad vitam aeternam in Christo elegerit ante jacta mundi fundamenta: consequens est, neminem suis operibus a Deo promereri ut eligatur” (ibid., 102).
  75. “Ut sunt qualificationes in persona salvanda requisitae adeoque habilitates subjecti ad salutem consequendam…. At hae qualitates sunt salvandorum, non propriae salutis” (Praelectiones, 233).
  76. “Conditiones salutis assequendae” (ibid.).
  77. “Ut sine quibus salutem non assequimur, licet non sint tales conditiones effectivae, ex quarum efficientia propria salus acquiritur” (ibid.).
  78. “Cum enim conditiones in contractibus duplicis sint generis, vel antecedentes, quae causam dant contractui, eiusque fundamentum & essentiam constituunt: vel consequentes, quae adduntur praecedentibus, quae contractus essentiam non constituunt, & mutuae licet sint, alterutram tamen partem obligant” (ibid.).
  79. “Quarum haec natura & vis est, ut licet earum praesentia salutem non efficiat, absentia tamen eam impedire queat” (ibid.).
  80. “Temperantia non efficit sapientiam, aliter omnis temperans sapiens foret, at eius absentia sapientiam impedit” (ibid.).
  81. “Cum vero fides salvifica sanctitate & bonis operibus semper & necessario stipata sit, ex horum tanquam conditionum absentia ipsa fides omnino abesse necessario intelligitur, unde nulla salus esse potest, sed certa perditio” (ibid.).
  82. “Ut sunt media salutis administrantia … quae nequaquam nullam omnino ad salutem affectionem habent” (ibid.).
  83. “Zanchius ea causas vult instrumentales non ipsius salutis per ea efficiendae” (ibid.).
  84. “Sunt via ad Regnum, sed non causa regnandi” (ibid.).
  85. “Ut vestis nuptialis conviviam adeundi, non ipsas conficiendi nuptias” (ibid.).
  86. “Ut summatim dicam, Relationem habent ordinis, qualem habent media ad finem, antecedens ad consequens, causa sine qua non, ad effectum, at non causae proprie effectivae salutis vel retinendae, ut aliqui volunt, multo minus vel physice efficiendae, vel moraliter, h.e. meritorie acquirendae” (ibid., 233–34).
  87. “Caveamus itaque ne dum ita toti in Antinomos insurgamus, in Pontificiorum castra sensim transire, vel saltem iis faventiores esse videamur” (ibid., 234).

John Wallis’s “Brief and Easie Explanation” in the Context of Catechesis in Early Modern England

By Jacob Thielman

[Jacob Thielman is a doctoral student in systematic and philosophical theology at Calvin Theological Seminary in Grand Rapids, MI.]

ABSTRACT

John Wallis (1616–1703), the contentious polymath and developer of infinitesimal calculus, published the very first explication of the Westminster Shorter Catechism in 1648. As one of the scribes at the Westminster Assembly, Wallis was in a unique position to write such an explication. This article argues that Wallis wrote his simplified catechism out of the pedagogical concerns that emerged through the English catechetical tradition of the mid sixteenth and early seventeenth centuries. Wallis’s Brief and Easie Explanation reduces the catechism to yes/no questions, a method touted by the renowned catechist Herbert Palmer, but not, of course, finally adopted by the committee. By bringing back into use the rejected method, Wallis was not quarreling with the Assembly’s decision, but putting the Palmer method into circulation as another aid to disseminating the Assembly’s teaching. After sifting through the text and finding no theological innovation, this article concludes that Wallis’s concerns were not theological but educational. Wallis was aware of the need for plain teaching and the debate surrounding catechesis. The controversy over pedagogy and the way it drove new innovations serves to highlight the common thrust of the movement to consolidate and purvey the English Reformation; even those who disagreed with other methods of teaching nevertheless encouraged the common cause represented in the proliferation of methods. Wallis’s Brief and Easie Explanation is therefore a peaceable contribution to the work of reform, and meticulously faithful to the results of the Westminster Assembly with which he was uniquely familiar.

---------------

“Few have deliberately questioned the value of catechising,” S. W. Carruthers pointed out half a century ago, though many have simply let it fall into disuse. On the other hand, the encomiums of the method are many.”[1]

While it is true that catechesis has nearly always been lauded and its absence lamented, in the two hundred tumultuous years after the 1530s, English catechesis truly began to flourish and catechisms themselves to proliferate.[2] What drove this proliferation was not simply a positive view of catechesis. The deluge was mainly produced by questions surrounding how catechesis should be conducted best in the service of what was, if the clergy are to be believed, an embattled reformation. If catechizing was the method of imparting religious knowledge, the methodology of this method (to put it in modern terms) underwent intense scrutiny. John Wallis’s catechism of 1648, while certainly successful—going through eight different printings—was more than just another instance of this trend.[3] It was unique for two reasons: (1) it was the very first of many pedagogical supplements to the 1647 Westminster Shorter Catechism, and (2) Wallis was in a unique position to explicate the catechism, having been present for almost the entire Westminster Assembly.[4]

Wallis is not widely known as a catechist except perhaps among historians of the period. He is mainly recognized for everything that happened thereafter—his work as a code breaker for Parliament, his founding role in the Royal Society, his prolific letters and publications providing real contributions to an astonishing number of disciplines, and perhaps most of all his invention of infinitesimal calculus.[5] In view of such an extraordinary life, it is tempting to scour Wallis’s catechism (one of his first publications) for theological innovation, but this search would yield nothing of the kind. In fact, what one finds—which is perhaps even more consistent with the character of Wallis’s other works—is a deep concern for pedagogy. Wallis was not concerned in this document with the wise, but the simple. It is the burden of this article to situate Wallis’s work within the trend of growing pedagogical awareness of his time, and to show that Wallis was aware of his unique historical position and used it to contribute to the body of catechetical literature at a key moment. We will discover that Wallis’s awareness led him not into theological disputation, but into the fray of pedagogical considerations.

I. Historiography and Reformation England

John Wallis’s catechism cannot be viewed solely as an explanation of the WSC; it must be located within the broader context of catechesis in this period. One might even say that the title’s emphasis should land not on “explanation” but on “brief and easie.” The massive shifts in historiography surrounding the English Reformation since the 1980s have given catechesis a particularly prominent role.[6] Revisionists Eamon Duffy, Jack Scarisbrick, and Christopher Haigh have added depth and complexity to the history of this period by sifting through the records of parishes and churchwardens. These more mundane accounts of religious life in sixteenth-century England presented a significant challenge to the inherited Protestant and national narratives, which tended to view this entire period as the (mostly) uninterrupted march of Protestantism from its official conception under Henry VIII to a resounding victory under Elizabeth.[7] The relevance to the process of catechesis should be obvious, for while the formation of catechisms and perhaps some opinions on the spiritual state of the average parishioner’s mind might appear in a sweeping narrative of great men and events, the details of how and why catechesis was actually performed or how any given method fared is bound to appear in greater relief at the local level. According to Haigh (following Gerald Strauss), catechesis itself is one of the ways the success or failure of the Reformation in England can be gauged, both then and now.[8]

This view is not without its skeptics and critics, of course. Haigh’s essay on success and failure in the English Reformation follows in the footsteps of Strauss’s work on the Reformation in Germany, asking whether clergy (as opposed to modern evaluators) believed the Reformation to have succeeded.[9] Peter Marshall writes, “One is tempted to observe here that ‘success and failure’ seems less an attempt to engage comparatively with debates on the historiography of Reformation Germany than a concept chosen for the facility with which it could be mapped onto a preexisting set of revisionist presumptions and concerns.”[10] Marshall’s suspicion, which may be overwrought, is that Haigh is basically setting up the English Reformation for failure in his account, even if Haigh concedes (reluctantly, on Marshall’s reading) that catechesis of a sort did take hold, if only as rote memorization. This evaluation is not entirely fair, since, at least with regard to its progress, the clerics’ view of the Reformation in a sense was the view of the Reformation at the time, and its success was absolutely their concern (more, one must imagine, than it is Haigh’s, or that of any modern historian). What the effects of this generalized clerical pessimism might have been is another matter entirely. Placing Wallis’s catechism into this scholarly context, the question becomes whether we can view it as a sort of “victory lap” for the Westminster Assembly, or whether it is not engaged in a broader controversy about catechetical method; the answer actually lies somewhere in between.

Marshall goes on to observe that English Reformation history has purportedly passed into a post-revisionist phase, one largely embraced by Haigh, where the term “The English Reformation” is no longer considered sufficient as it denotes a single, cohesive whole.[11] Instead, the religious upheavals of this century are viewed through the porous, complex, abortive—in a word, human—components that characterized the nation’s multivalent attempts at Protestantism. One can obviously take this recasting too far, moving from the correct eschewal of whiggish history in favor of better methodology to disjunctive atomization which cuts through movements that really did hang together in the minds of the participants. Marshall is undoubtedly correct that the Reformation was at least “a central perception and organizing category of the contemporaries themselves,” even if it was a term constructed from the Protestant standpoint.[12] It is a truism that one can simultaneously hold in one’s mind the contingency of a term and still use it without misunderstanding.

However, a particular point is in order about the terms “success” and “failure” in the context of catechesis: John Wallis’s catechism (like all the other Protestant catechisms) was undoubtedly aimed at promoting the success of the Reformation in England, regardless of any actual success. It was not written in competition with the WSC, but rather for its advancement. I think Marshall is wise to suggest that some of the controversy over whiggish or confessional history might be ameliorated simply by noting that these are processes of religious identity formation.[13] In fact, Haigh agrees on this point: what counts more than our modern evaluations is whether contemporary pastors themselves believed they had succeeded.[14] I would simply add that it also counts whether they believed they were succeeding even as they tried different ways of achieving their aims.

That this process of identity formation accounts for both diversity and cogency is underscored by what Ian Green calls “the English Catechetical Tradition.” From the mid sixteenth century until the beginning of the seventeenth, the predominant attitude towards catechisms was “the more the merrier,” which abated somewhat in the decades prior to the Westminster Assembly. There was another surge during the 1640s and 1650s when the Assembly took place (and Wallis’s explanation appeared), and limited production of catechisms continued through the rest of the century.[15] As we will see, the primary force driving the explosion of catechisms in this period was pedagogical. Thus, for our purposes of understanding the context of Wallis’s catechism, Marshall’s observation is apt: when Protestant writers used the phrase “the reformation of the church,” they were referring to a work in progress.[16]

II. Trends in Catechesis Prior to Westminster

In 1882, Alexander Mitchell quipped, “It may fairly be said of the catechisms framed on the system of the doctrinal Puritans, and published in England between the years 1600 and 1645, that their name is legion.”[17] This is no exaggeration. In his authoritative 1996 survey of catechisms and the form and method of catechizing in early modern England, Ian Green does the difficult work of actually tallying the number of catechisms and catechetical works published in England during the period from 1530 to 1740.[18] The number he reaches is no less than 1,043. There are several historiographical difficulties in coming up with this number, including the definition of a catechism, lost texts, incomplete lists, and publishers and catechists bringing texts in from other countries. All of these issues tend to cause estimates to be on the low side, so Green states that his figure is to be regarded as a minimum.[19]

We will explore two main trends in method and practice amid this sea of texts, trends which are an important prelude to the Westminster Assembly and the documents it produced. First, we will see that the clergy were increasingly concerned with moral and doctrinal laxity reflected in the state of catechesis among their parishioners, which might also be called a concern for the success of the English Reformation. Then we will trace the development of more effective pedagogical methods with the growing number of catechisms as an attempt to curb this perceived spiritual decline.

1. The Clerical Fight Against Poor Catechesis

“There was only one test of religious knowledge in Elizabethan England,” declares Haigh, and this was the 1549 Prayer Book (or Book of Common Prayer) catechism.[20] Largely the work of the Puritan Alexander Nowell, its catechisms came in three varieties: short, middle, and large.[21] It was the short catechism in particular that remained the standard of training in orthodoxy until the WSC revised it in 1646.[22] In the period marked off by these two documents, however, more than five hundred different catechetical forms were produced in England.[23] These new forms were produced to effect an improvement in catechesis. Green postulates that the growth of anti-Catholic sentiment played a role in this concern with proper catechizing.[24] Complaints about the Prayer Book’s short catechism also came from “more dogmatic Calvinists,” who found both its doctrine and its form inadequate.[25] The result was that hundreds of “unofficial” catechisms were produced over the next century.[26] Green suggests that Gerald Strauss’s comparison of catechesis with education in general in the German context be emulated in the English context, a challenge which C. John Sommerville takes up (and which we will explore in the next section).[27] It is something of a red herring to separate doctrinal and educational concerns, but we will see that there is clearly a methodological difference between indoctrination and education.

It is not enough to say these catechisms were simply a product of some caricatured Puritan legalism. Puritan or evangelical religion (to which Wallis subscribed) certainly emphasized right doctrine, but its focus was the heart and its attitudes. Richard Greenham spoke characteristically when he said he was mainly concerned “to stir up the heart, and to quicken affections to embrace true godlinesse.”[28] In fact, Puritans were not the only ones concerned with right catechesis. The Prayer Book itself barred those who were not properly catechized from communion. It contained “a prescribed formula of warning: ‘My duty is to exhort you to consider the dignity of the holy mystery and the great peril of the unworthy receiving thereof, and so to search and examine your own consciences, as you should come holy and clean to a most godly and heavenly feast.’”[29] Worthiness was explicitly linked with knowledge of the catechism. Exclusion from communion was the penalty for “any aged over twenty-four who cannot ‘say by heart’ the Ten Commandments, the Creed and the Lord’s Prayer, and any between fourteen and twenty-four who cannot say the Prayer Book catechism by heart,” according to the injunctions of Archbishop Grindal, which became standard in the Elizabethan episcopacy.[30] It is only with this concern for right hearts (and not just right doctrine) in mind that we can really understand the concerns that pushed catechetical development in early modern England.

While there was plenty of (much bemoaned) laxity in catechizing, with various culprits being named, from poor administration by ministers to lackadaisical parenting, there is also an abundance of documented cases of enforcement.[31] In fact, rejection from communion on the grounds of inadequate catechizing had become common (and contentious) in some dioceses in the late sixteenth century.[32] This enforcement and discord created an administrative record which Haigh uses to trace the movement for reform and analyze its results. He finds that clergy most often drew links between the (ongoing) failure of the Reformation and moral failures or spiritual decline in their congregations.[33] Some placed the blame squarely on parents and schoolmasters for not teaching “Christian moral values,”[34] which certainly referred to poor catechesis. While the focus is on children and youth, it is clear that at times the elders could be just as indifferent.[35]

While the clergy were never optimistic about catechesis (a point to which we will return in a moment), the obverse side of this pessimism is that the clerical efforts at reform driven by this outlook did seem to make a difference. Haigh identifies two measures in which this is so: on the one hand, as the records progress, the age of those who could not say the catechism decreases. He cites reports between 1569 and 1622 that suggest that after a generation, “a large majority now fulfilled the requirement by the time they were adult and were admitted to communion.”[36] The records from which Haigh is working seem to be reporting from different parishes in different times, and he notes beforehand that there were many gaps in the reporting, but the general picture is persuasive, especially given the ministers’ tendency toward negative evaluation. His second measure is more subtle: there appear to be changing expectations in the reports around catechizing as time goes on, such that failure to recite the catechism had become an embarrassment. Knowing the catechism had been rare before, but it had clearly become normalized enough by the early 1600s to be expected.[37]

Thus, Haigh can conclude, “The Church of England had achieved one great educational success: it had taught its people the catechism.”[38] But the ministers did not believe a memorized catechism was enough. Richard Kilby (1561?–1620) said of his own upbringing, “I was a little taught outward religion,” and that most people thought this superficial knowledge was enough at the time, such was the poor state of religious education.[39] The belief that religious education and its results were so poor is particularly important leading up to the Westminster Assembly, where precisely these evangelical ministers would be tasked with reforming the Reformed church.

2. The Development of Pedagogy Through Catechesis

If concern over moral laxity and the desire to evoke sincere belief drove catechetical development, this force also deepened the general understanding of education in Elizabethan England. Development of method itself was driven not just to see that doctrines lodge more clearly in the brain, but to address the state of actual belief. C. John Sommerville makes the distinction between education and indoctrination: education “showing an awareness of the child as an autonomous individual whose freedom ought to be respected,” and indoctrination, with its rote regurgitation of formulas, being somewhat the opposite.[40]

While these are modern terms, the awareness of this distinction clearly arises even in the most basic critical thinking about catechesis in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. One reason so many ministers felt the need to reform the Prayer Book’s two official catechisms was that “the first was too short and the other too long for the average catechumen,” a problem which developed into the need for completeness and for comprehension.[41] A further reason was to appeal to older and younger learners, a concern which eventually made its way right into the chambers of the Westminster Assembly.[42]

Sommerville makes a strong case that the Puritans became acutely cognizant of the effectiveness of different pedagogies for different levels of child development, education, and ability, and all this through the very practice of developing and implementing catechisms. Samuel Rutherford clearly knew the significance of catechetical method, noting at the Westminster Assembly’s debate over the Shorter Catechism that “there was ‘as much art in catechising as in anything in the world.’”[43] It is significant that this awareness arose among “Anglicans, Catholics, Puritans, Quakers, Socinians” who had no hope of imposing their views on all of England amid the ideological turmoil.[44] Unlike in the centuries prior to the Reformation, the knowledge and acceptance of doctrine was practically synonymous with the survival of each religious movement. This urgency was the engine of their pedagogical impulse, but it also created a concern for depth, since a religious movement could hardly be considered fertile if it could not reproduce sincere adherents. Thus, Sommerville claims that the principal reasons for writing new catechisms were greater simplicity or completeness, or more appealing or logical presentation. Both simplicity and completeness move in the same direction of greater understanding, and as with Wallis’s catechism, sometimes the simpler catechisms were meant to be aids for the more complete catechisms. “In short,” writes Sommerville, “the Puritans were responding to truly educational impulses.”[45]

Not only were the Puritans responding to truly educational impulses, they were doing so effectively. Memorization was a part, but not the whole, of catechesis. While it would obviously be anachronistic to read an understanding of modern psychological development back into pre-Westminster times, Green notes that the very issues that animated educational psychology in the mid to late twentieth century—debates over rote memorization, the value of memory work, ways to make concepts appropriate for children—were being debated by English catechists as early as the sixteenth century.[46] “Traditionally, catechizing was thought of more as a precondition of education than as part of the schooling process itself. Catechizing bore a relation to religious instruction similar to that which grammatical drill bore to the study of literature or the multiplication tables to the study of mathematics.”[47]

A “major step forward” came with Herbert Palmer’s Yes/No method, implemented in his 1640 work, An Endeavour of Making the Principles of Christian Religion … plaine and easie.[48] This method of supplementing main questions with much simpler yes or no questions was adopted by Wallis in his catechism, with an appreciative nod to Palmer. The Palmer/Wallis method represented a shift to “a reflective method which would draw the truth out of children rather than cram it in.”[49] It was certainly not the most radical pedagogical shift to take place—some catechisms had only twelve questions, some were conversational, and some emphasized narrative. Some demonstrated their doctrines from the works of creation, and there were even catechisms on catechesis.[50] However, the Palmer/Wallis method spawned many imitators, gaining widespread use.

It was in this environment, where catechesis had evolved over the course of an entire century under the pressures of seeking sincere belief resulting from effective education, that the Westminster Assembly met to reform the church and create a new shorter catechism. Among those present during this effort—indeed, the man charged with transcribing the Shorter Catechism—was John Wallis.

III. The Occasion for the “Brief and Easie Explanation”

On July 1, 1643, the Westminster Assembly met for the first time, tasked with reforming the “Liturgy, Discipline, and Government of the Church of England.”[51] It is not difficult to hear the impetus behind Edmund Calamy’s call not only to reform the Church of England of William Laud, but to “reform the Reformation it selfe.”[52] The primary doctrinal task of the Assembly was the revision of the Thirty-Nine Articles and the Prayer Book. This task was monumental, and I will not attempt a full description of it here. I will highlight those points in the development of the WSC that show both how it continued the century-long development of catechesis that preceded it and how John Wallis was (or was not) involved.

1. The Westminster Catechism as a Product of Catechetical Development

The task of producing a catechism (just one at first, presumably to replace those in the Prayer Book) was entrusted to Herbert Palmer in December 1643. Carruthers claims Palmer was “famous as the best catechist in England,” which, given the huge number of catechisms and their great variety and the vigorous debate about their merits, is a remarkable claim.[53] Palmer was also the fourth most frequent contributor (third most frequent speaker) at the Assembly itself, and not, therefore, an obscure or controversial choice.[54]

Robert Baillie (to whose habitual epistolary indiscretions historians owe a great debt) thought that the catechism would appear near the end of the following year.[55] Yet, after months of delays, the formation of a committee to expedite its work, and further optimism and consternation from committee members, nothing appeared. Only when the committee was ordered to meet “this afternoon” on May 12, 1645, did Palmer finally submit a report.[56] Not surprisingly, the catechism followed much the same methods of Palmer’s previous efforts, and it was the Yes/No method, not the content, which quickly became the subject of debate.[57]

Issues of pedagogical effectiveness, the considerations of the age and abilities of the catechumen, all now familiar to the development of pedagogy in the preceding century, arose immediately. Samuel Rutherford seemed to approve Palmer’s method, favoring its simplicity. Stephen Marshall, however, objected to the addition of Yes/No questions to the regular catechetical questions, arguing that they would result only in rote learning. William Bridge added a layer of pedagogical awareness by noting that catechizing is for both the increase and the testing of knowledge, and that the latter was not adequately addressed with just yes and no questions.[58]

After much debate and further exhortations, it became clear that the catechism could only be finished after the Confession was complete. Then, on January 14, 1647, the committee’s work was halted by a motion passed by the Assembly that the committee develop not one but two catechisms, “having an ey [sic] to” the Confession and the incomplete catechism.[59] The Yes/No method was abandoned after that.

Once the Larger Catechism was finally nearing completion that August, the committee for the Shorter Catechism was formed, and Palmer served as its chair. Work began September 16, but less than a month later, Herbert Palmer fell ill and died.[60] Carruthers asserts that production of the WSC is owed to John Lightfoot, Stephen Marshall, Jason Ward, and in particular Anthony Tuckney.[61] The draft of the Shorter Catechism was finally presented to the Assembly and debated during eight sessions between October 21 and November 9.[62] Then, interestingly, Carruthers says, “I wish I could accept the suggestion of Dr. [Alexander] Mitchell that the Catechism has ‘unmistakeable evidence of its having passed through the alembic of Dr. Wallis, the great mathematician,’ but, unhappily, he was not instructed to attend the committee till the work was practically done, on the 9th November, an instruction which would not have been given were he already in attendance.”[63] As we will see next, however, Wallis’s instruction to attend the committee at this late date hardly precludes his involvement.

2. John Wallis as an Expositor of the Westminster Shorter Catechism

It would be a mistake to conclude from the assignment of Wallis to the committee as its transcriber at this later date that he had nothing to do with the catechism until that point. The fact is that the divines met at all hours, not just at the Assembly. Some of them lived together, and others commuted from surrounding neighborhoods over the many years that the Assembly was at work.[64] The Westminster Assembly was not just a formal work, but a way of life for those who were called to be a part of it. Some moved their families, struggled to work at other jobs, prepared sermons, and carried on a whole supplementary existence around the abbey.[65] Wallis himself, according to his autobiography, was in his twenties and working as a minister in London during his time at the Assembly.[66] He writes, “Wherein [as a secretary] I do own myself to have received much advantage by the Conversation and the learned Debates of so many Grave, Reverend and Learned Divines, on all points of Divinity, wh[en] they were compiling the Confession of Faith, and the Larger and lesser Catechism.”[67] Such conversations (not just debates!) were common—indeed, the whole country was abuzz with the work at Westminster while it continued.

It is therefore not at all hard to conclude that Wallis was involved in the work of the confession and knew it quite well. Indeed, it is difficult to explain why he would immediately publish his supplement to it had he been uninvolved or had no opinions about it. Mitchell claims that Wallis “in all likelihood had been privately assisting his friend Palmer with [the catechism] during the last weeks of his life.”[68] For support, he notes that Wallis was a fellow in Queen’s College, where Palmer was a master.[69] While it is probably an exaggeration that the catechism evidently “passed through the alembic of Dr. Wallis,” it is actually quite unlikely that Wallis was uninvolved with the catechism, given how deeply immersed he was in the larger process. More to the point even than this, in the preface to his Brief and Easie Explanation Wallis claims to have had “an intimate acquaintance” with Palmer.[70]

In the preface to the document Wallis immediately acknowledges that his catechism is “in a method somewhat unusual.”[71] He ascribes his method to Herbert Palmer, and makes careful note that it was “intertained [sic] with great approbation” by the Assembly.[72] Wallis claims simply to be fulfilling Palmer’s own desire to have the catechism published, if not by the Assembly then “by some private hand,” and “was fully resolved to have done it himself,” but died before he got the chance.[73] Moreover, Wallis, who is clearly an admirer of Palmer, subtly makes the argument that Palmer was right by noting that the catechism was intended for public use. It was a common criticism of catechisms in England at this time, and especially of the WSC, that they should be made accessible to lay minds.[74] However common this criticism was subsequently, however, Wallis’s catechism was in fact the very first “explanation” of the WSC, appearing “almost instantly,” just two years after the WSC’s initial publication.[75]

Wallis was in a good—possibly the best—position to be a theological expositor of the catechism, and demonstrated an awareness of this fact. Not only is there the circumstantial evidence of the catechism itself (namely, that Wallis saw the opportunity and undertook the task of writing it at all), there is also its position as the first ever exposition of the WSC (with hundreds to follow), and as we will see, its correspondence with debates internal to the Assembly. There is also the evidence of his autobiography.

At the age of eighty, Wallis wrote a short autobiography for his friend Thomas Smith.[76] Wallis certainly talks about mathematics and his career, but with great modesty, given the staggering number and depth of his accomplishments. More surprising is the fact that he uses most of his space on two portions of his life: his time at the Westminster Assembly, specifically justifying its purpose, and his development of a grammar to teach the deaf how to speak.[77] Wallis clearly regarded himself as an authority on the Westminster Assembly. He writes, “There are not many now living, who can give a better account of that Assembly than I can.”[78] This was obviously a plausible claim in 1687. Yet not just his age, but his status as a scribe gave him unique insight into what went on there. What is interesting for this article is that Wallis cared to cast himself in this light, and to do so even in his later years.

Moreover, the trends in catechesis we have outlined are present conceptually in Wallis’s thoughts. In the original draft, Wallis writes, “For it was always my desire from a child, in all faculties not onely [sic] to learn Rules by rote, but to understand the [sense and the] true Meaning, and the Reasons of them.”[79] Wallis’s English grammar, which he thought to be very original, was attempting to advance current ideas about speech and its components, and he believed he could use this research to teach a deaf person to speak.[80] At one point, he actually sought out such a man by the name of Alexander Popham—and proceeded to teach him (for a fee) to speak in a little over a year.[81] He was not satisfied with poor pronunciation, seeking complete and distinct pronunciation. He also taught Popham to read and write from the English Bible. He taught another deaf man the following year and even kept up with both men well enough to comment on their retention and his own continued help.[82]

Before turning to the text itself, there is one more way in which Wallis is a unique expositor of the WSC. Even while the Westminster Assembly was working on its two catechisms, more elementary versions were being produced by other Puritans such as Robert Abbott, John Cotton, and Isaac Watts.[83] These men were not competing with the Assembly either (it is obvious by now that catechesis was a broadly used form almost regardless of the religious content), but neither were they tasked with creating the Assembly’s official catechisms. There were twenty-four men besides Wallis who had some contact with the various catechism committees.[84] Many of them created catechisms of their own, some before and some after the Assembly. Of these, there is not one work dedicated simply to elucidating the WSC. Wallis’s work is unique in this regard, and one would be hard-pressed to find someone more qualified to elucidate the questions themselves. We should turn, then, to the text of his explanation, and ask what it was that he felt needed elucidation.

IV. An Examination of Wallis’s Catechism

In writing an explanation of the WSC with a different, more expansive method, Wallis was simply making an effort to elucidate what he thought to be too difficult for some catechumens. Wallis’s concerns were not radical; they were simply pedagogical, and there is no evidence that they were a product of his famed contentiousness.

The first evidence that Wallis was working from pedagogical concerns in line with the current debates about catechesis (besides the title itself) is the imprimatur of Edmund Calamy, a leader and widely respected member of the Assembly.[85] It is hard to imagine that such a text would have received his endorsement if it represented some contentious or contradictory goal to the Assembly itself. After his tribute to Palmer, Wallis goes on to assert that he has included the “Assemblies Catechism” and its Scripture proofs in their entirety and unchanged. The WSC’s method includes answers which do not rely on the questions themselves, but may be confessed independently—a pedagogical consideration meant to aid the learner’s memory.[86] Wallis explains that he has merely added yes or no questions which point directly to components of the Assembly’s answers, and these are explanations directed toward “weak capacities.”[87]

All which is done without charging the learners memory, for to answer these short questions, is not so much an exercise of memory, as of the judgement, being able to distinguish between truth and falsehood, assenting to the one and denying the other; Yea, the memory is much helped by it, there being nothing in the general Answer, but what they are put in minde of, by some of the Questions.[88]

Wallis is tapping into a number of concerns we have shown to be present in his day. He expresses the concern that rote memorization does not lead to real understanding. He wants learners to accept what they understand and to practice it for themselves. He even makes the remarkable (perhaps proto-modern) educational point that one’s memory is actually helped by the interested use of one’s own judgment—that, in effect, the ability to use one’s judgment to answer simple questions can bring the simple learner to remember the more substantive question. All this is verified by Wallis’s instruction to the catechist to read the answer, ask the Yes/No questions, and then go back and ask the main question.[89]

Most of the time, as Wallis’s exposition progresses, he keeps to his word and addresses only that which is explicitly mentioned in the text. There are incidental issues in the text, such as several confusing double negatives that may simply reflect the vernacular (“Shall [God] never have an end? No.”).[90] It is also clear that Wallis draws from his own good sense on certain matters, as when, for example, he expands on the nature of God’s infinity by saying he has no bounds in place, time, or perfection.[91] Sometimes his questions reiterate the answer word for word, broken up into phrases for individual assent. Other times, Wallis imports some obvious counterexamples to make a point clear. For example:

2. Q. What rule hath God given to direct us how we may glorifie and enjoy him? 

A: The word of God which is contained in the books of the Old and New Testament, is the only rule to direct us how we may glorifie and enjoy him. 

Can we receive sufficient direction from our own wisdom, or the light of nature? No 

Or, From Gods works of Creation and Providence only? No 

Or, Is the Word of God the only Rule? Yes 

Or, Must we daily expect new Revelations from Heaven? No 

Is that the word of God which is contained in the Scriptures of the Old and New Testament? Yes 

Or, somewhat else? No[92]

There are, however, places where Wallis does not straightforwardly elucidate the answer without any imported thoughts. It would seem that the learner is “put in mind of” quite a few things which are not contained in the answer itself, were one simply to pick up the WSC and read it without any background. There is usually a mundane explanation for each of these moments. Sometimes this is a rigorization of the WSC answer—sin, in answer to question 14, is not just “want of conformity unto, or transgression of the law of God,” but “any” such want, “even in the smallest matters,” including not just some but every single transgression.[93] Sometimes Wallis works from the Scripture proofs to elucidate the meaning of the catechism’s text. Other times, as in his treatment of effectual calling (question 31), Wallis’s Yes/No questions at first seem to create unintended obverse sides to the stated doctrine—asking, in this example, whether any are called who are not made aware of their sin and misery (“No”).[94] Extending the assertion that the Holy Spirit makes us aware of our sin to say that none who are called are not made aware of their sin suggests a sort of ordo salutis not present in the WSC doctrine. Yet a glance at the Westminster Confession and even the Larger Catechism reveals that Wallis has outlined precisely the intention behind the doctrine, though it is treated under the subject of Justification in these sources. Perhaps there is room for debate here, but it would be tendentious to call the Explanation heterodox at this point. More to the point, each of these movements—rigorization, working from Scripture, and importing content from the Assembly itself—is much more clearly pedagogical than theological, even though there is definite theological content in play.

The one issue where Wallis might seem to be innovating or digressing is in how he treats the sinlessness of Christ. There are more questions surrounding this issue than others, and it appears to arise even when WSC is not explicitly addressing it. Question 16 asks, “Did all mankind fall in Adams [sic] first transgression? A: The covenant being made with Adam, not only for himself, but for his posterity, all mankinde descending from him by ordinary generation, fell with him in his first transgression.” Wallis’s first question of clarification is, “Did Christ fall as well as others? No.”[95] The clause “by ordinary generation,” seems to imply that Christ is excepted from the fall, even though Christ is never mentioned, as Christ is the only possible exception to ordinary generation. In Question 22, on Christ’s becoming man, the answer is, “Christ the Son of God became man, by taking to himself a true body, and a reasonable soul, being conceived by the Holy Ghost, in the womb of the virgin Mary, and born of her, yet without sin.”[96] Amid his elucidations, Wallis writes, “Was he conceived and born without sin? Yes.”[97] The phrasing of the answer is ambiguous as to whether it is Christ Himself who was without sin, or whether it was his conception and birth which were without sin, the difference being the question of whether original sin and the curse of the fall were imputed to Jesus himself (concepts set out in question 18). Question 82 is most problematic of all, as the question is, “Is any man able perfectly to keep the commandments of God?”[98] Christ is not mentioned in the answer, but seeing a potential contradiction, Wallis supplies the following; “Was not Christ able to do it in this life? Yes. And, was he not mear [sic] man? No. Or, Was he God, as well as man? Yes.”[99]

It would appear that Wallis is determined to assert that Jesus was not subject to the effects of the fall anywhere that the converse might be implied in the WSC. An uncharitable reading might even find hints of Arianism in his explications. A deeper exploration reveals precisely the opposite. The Assembly actually debated this question on the floor—a rarity, as most of these debates took place in undocumented committees—and the minutes show a few transitional forms. Interestingly, the verbatim phrase “Christ was conceived and borne ‘withouit [sic] sin,” was proposed and rejected during the proceedings.[100] It is easy to make too much of such a common theological phrase, but it is noteworthy given Wallis’s presence at the Assembly.[101] The final form in the Larger Catechism is hardly different from Question 22 of WSC. Wallis is clearly familiar with the debate, and his concern about the sinlessness of Christ, read with proper charity, seems in line with the final conclusions of the Assembly. Chapter 8 of the Westminster Confession, “Of Christ the Mediator,” notes both the sinlessness and the human infirmity of Christ.[102] Further, in paragraph 3, the Confession states that Christ was sanctified and anointed by the Holy Spirit (and it makes special note of his united human and divine nature) “to the end that, being holy, harmless, undefiled, and full of grace and truth, He might be thoroughly furnished to execute the office of a Mediator and Surety.” It is certainly within the bounds of the Confession’s theology to argue that Christ’s sinlessness was due in part to the inapplicability of the fall to the Son of God. While we cannot necessarily verify that Wallis was pulling from the Assembly’s own work in this instance, there is evidence enough to suggest that he was, and we certainly cannot refute this claim.

V. Conclusion

It should be clear that the first exposition of the WSC was motivated by educational concerns. It was, moreover, very successful. The Yes/No method spawned many imitators.[103] Among those who adopted the method were Joseph Alleine, Thomas Doolittle, Samuel Angier, and Matthew Henry.[104] While it gained widespread use, one criticism of this method was that it resulted in the pursuit of wrong answers, while being satisfied with correct ones, and this legalism was, in fact, a problem.[105] What should be noted is that amid controversies about confessional or whiggish histories of Reformation England, more careful study of the texts and what gave them rise can actually reveal confessional harmony borne out in secondary concerns, such as the education of children. We certainly have not discovered a triumphant march of Protestantism through England. On the contrary, we have discovered a highly intentional reformation brought about by diligence, insight, and no small degree of anxiety. Wallis, who apparently could hardly have been a more contentious human being throughout his life after Westminster, was engaged in the productive work of bringing Westminster’s orthodoxy to the children and the simple in local parishes. Even in itself, this fact is remarkable.

There is a temptation to write the history of any period in terms of its great upheavals, highlighting the exciting, combative parts of the narrative as the moments that truly moved history, but if the revisionist mode of thinking and its progeny teach us anything, it ought to be that history is made quietly and locally, even if these events finally add up to the clash of faiths and civilizations. Perhaps it is harder to write quiet history these days, but it is worth it to ask whether a critical reappraisal of our confessional histories might not turn up works of mercy and clear thought as easily as atrocities and ideology.

Notes

  1. S. W. Carruthers, Three Centuries of the Westminster Shorter Catechism (Fredericton, New Brunswick: University of New Brunswick, 1957), 7.
  2. These years include the English Civil War and the official and unofficial attempts to reform the Church of England. This is roughly the period chosen by Ian Green for his definitive survey of English catechesis: Ian Green, The Christian’s ABC: Catechisms and Catechizing in England, c. 1530–1740 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996).
  3. John Wallis, A Brief and Easie explanation of the Shorter catechisme presented by the Assembly of Divines at Westminster, to both Houses of Parliament, and by them approved. Wherein the meanest capacities may in a speedy and easie way be brought to understand the principles of religion. In imitation of a catechisme formerly published, by Mr. Herbert Palmer B.D. and late Master of Queens College. By J.W. Minister of the Gospel, 1st ed. (London, 1648). This edition can be found at Early English Books Online.
  4. Hereafter, Westminster Shorter Catechism is abbreviated as WSC. Carruthers lists the first edition of the Westminster Confession and its catechisms as published in 1648 (Carruthers, Three Centuries, 53), but the original document as November 1647, when it was presented to Parliament. Wallis was added to the Assembly’s team of scribes as an assistant in 1643, serving an increasingly prominent role until its conclusion (Chad Van Dixhoorn, ed., The Minutes and Papers of the Westminster Assembly, 1643–1652, 5 vols. [Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012], 5:27–28, 1:142–43).
  5. See, e.g., J. F. Scott, “The Reverend John Wallis, F. R. S.,” Notes and Records of the Royal Society of London 15 (July 1960): 57–67. Here Wallis’s time at Westminster is mentioned only once, and it is portrayed as merely delaying his career in mathematics. Neither his catechism nor any of his theology is mentioned.
  6. A note on proper nouns and adjectives: throughout, the word “Reformation” is capitalized when referring to a proper noun, especially the Reformation in general, the English Reformation, or adjectivally as in “Reformation Germany.” This is to help differentiate between the movement as it was conceived by its participants and referred to later by historians from the more recent attempts to speak of “reform movements” and “reformations” that may be referenced independently.
  7. Peter Marshall, “(Re)defining the English Reformation,” Journal of British Studies 48 (2009): 565.
  8. Christopher Haigh, “Success and Failure in the English Reformation,” Past and Present 173 (November 2001): 28–35.
  9. Gerald Strauss, “Success and Failure in the German Reformation,” Past and Present 67 (May 1975): 30–63.
  10. Marshall, “(Re)defining the English Reformation,” 577.
  11. Ibid., 565–66.
  12. Ibid., 569. Marshall later goes into recent skirmishes over supposed confessional biases, noting the obvious fact that religious belief (or I would add, belief or nonbelief of any kind) can hardly be made out to be an unequivocal, much less quantifiable, liability to a historian working diligently in the field. Similarly, Haigh himself has pointed out that even if we may re-evaluate the success of the Reformation using modern tools, ensuing events cannot be explained without acknowledging that English clergy believed that they had failed (Haigh, “Success and Failure,” 48–49).
  13. Marshall, “(Re)defining the English Reformation,” 583–84.
  14. Haigh, “Success and Failure,” 34–35, 49.
  15. Green, Christian’s ABC, 76–78. Green notes a period of decline after Westminster in which most catechisms were written in explanation of either the Prayer Book or the WSC, depending on whether one was inside or outside the official church. This abatement could have been due to changing views, such as the notion that proliferation of catechisms could lead to heterodoxy. Another factor could have been Laudian censorship, thought to be especially hard on Calvinist authors, though Green finds this unlikely, given the predominance of famed Calvinists among the catechetical authors during these decades.
  16. Marshall, “(Re)defining the English Reformation,” 570.
  17. Alexander Mitchell, The Westminster Assembly: Its History and Standards: Being the Baird Lecture for 1882, 2nd ed. (Philadelphia: Presbyterian Board of Publication and Sabbath-School Work, 1897), 419.
  18. Green, Christian’s ABC, 45–59.
  19. Ibid., 50.
  20. Haigh, “Success and Failure in the English Reformation,” 41. Green begins his survey in 1530, and notes some catechetical works prior even to this with a helpful account of the evolution of the term “catechism” and the precursors of the standard interrogative form that typically comes to the modern mind; see esp. Green, Christian’s ABC, 13–21.
  21. C. John Sommerville, “The Distinction between Indoctrination and Education in England, 1549–1719,” JHI 44 (1983): 389.
  22. Ian Green, “For Children in Yeeres and Children in Understanding: The Emergence of the English Catechism Under Elizabeth and the Early Stuarts,” JEH 37 (1986): 401.
  23. Green, Christian’s ABC, 51: Table 1. Green’s “For Children in Yeeres,” written ten years earlier, puts the number at over 350.
  24. Green, “For Children in Yeeres,” 401.
  25. Ibid.
  26. Sommerville, “Distinction between Indoctrination and Education,” 389.
  27. Green, “For Children in Yeeres,” 401.
  28. Bruce Hindmarsh, The Evangelical Conversion Narrative: Spiritual Autobiography in Early Modern England (New York: Oxford University Press, 2005), 34.
  29. Christopher Haigh, “Communion and Community: Exclusion from Communion in Post-Reformation England,” JEH 51 (2000): 724.
  30. Ibid., 722.
  31. Haigh, “Success and Failure in the English Reformation,”41–42.
  32. Ibid., 43. See also Haigh, “Communion and Community.”
  33. Haigh, “Success and Failure in the English Reformation,” 28–34.
  34. Ibid., 30, referring to the evaluation of Josias Nichols (1555?–1639).
  35. Haigh quotes one particularly meticulous report, giving its most dire estimation of the Woolbeding parish, “All that be under twenty years cannot say the catechism” (“Success and Failure in the English Reformation,” 38). Haigh adds, “It is unlikely that their elders could either.”
  36. Ibid., 45.
  37. Ibid.
  38. Ibid., 47.
  39. Ibid., 48.
  40. Sommerville, “Distinction between Indoctrination and Education,” 387. Sommerville acknowledges the possible anachronism. Puritans were not interested in “opening minds,” of course, but they did begin to acknowledge and work with children’s varied levels of development. For the Puritan mindset stated above, an educational center which results in the true acceptance of ideas by the individual is crucial to an effective catechism. Thus, while pedagogy and real education can be distinguished conceptually, some account must be taken of concern for sincerity as a sixteenth-century way of expressing an educational impulse.
  41. Green, “For Children in Yeeres,” 405.
  42. Ibid., 408.
  43. Carruthers, Three Centuries, 4.
  44. Sommerville,“Distinction between Indoctrination and Education,” 387.
  45. Ibid., 389.
  46. Green, “For Children in Yeeres,” 230–33.
  47. Sommerville, “Distinction between Indoctrination and Education,” 388.
  48. Ibid., 391.
  49. Ibid.
  50. Ibid., 390–91.
  51. Carruthers, Three Centuries, 3.
  52. Edmund Calamy, Englands looking-glasse (London, 1642), 23; cited in Van Dixhoorn, Minutes and Papers, 1:4.
  53. Carruthers, Three Centuries, 3.
  54. Van Dixhoorn, Minutes and Papers, 1:131, 213, citing the Oxford Dictionary of National Biography.
  55. Van Dixhoorn, Minutes and Papers, 1:108, citing the Oxford Dictionary of National Biography; Carruthers, Three Centuries, 3.
  56. Carruthers, Three Centuries, 3.
  57. Mitchell, Westminster Assembly, 425.
  58. Carruthers, Three Centuries, 4; Van Dixhoorn, Minutes and Papers, 3:598–600.
  59. Van Dixhoorn, Minutes and Papers, 4:399.
  60. Carruthers, Three Centuries, 4–5.
  61. Ibid., 5.
  62. Carruthers, Three Centuries, 5; Van Dixhoorn, Minutes and Papers, 4:698–703.
  63. Carruthers, Three Centuries, 5; reference to Mitchell, Westminster Assembly, 441.
  64. Van Dixhoorn, Minutes and Papers, 1:40–41.
  65. Ibid., 1:1. Van Dixhoorn adds many helpful details, and among them is this: “Enough members were enjoying themselves that rules were made about laughter in the assembly. Others began to complain under the strain of the many hours of work behind the writing, editing, submission, and too frequent rejection of assembly documents” (1:1–2). It is all too easy to forget, amid the formal product and historical impact of the Assembly, what a deeply contingent and human endeavor it was.
  66. Christoph J. Scriba, “The Autobiography of John Wallis, F.R.S,” Notes and Records of the Royal Society of London 25 (1970): 37.
  67. Ibid., 31–32.
  68. Mitchell, Westminster Assembly, 439.
  69. Ibid., 439n1.
  70. Wallis, Brief and Easie Explanation, A3.
  71. Ibid., A3r. Within the text of the catechism, collation marks are accompanied by the number of the question or answer on the following page (e.g., 7.Q. 7.A.). There are also page numbers in the upper-outside corners beginning with the actual catechism. References will be to page numbers where available and collation marks otherwise. It should also be noted that in the original text, questions are printed in the left column, catechism answers in the right, and yes/no answers in a thin, delineated middle column. Thus, the horizontal reworkings below, while not opposed to Wallis’s stated intentions, are not taken directly from the text.
  72. Ibid., A3v.
  73. Ibid.
  74. Green, Christian’s ABC, 82.
  75. Ibid.
  76. Scriba’s transcription of the autobiography helpfully lays out both an original draft and the final, much revised and expanded version. Christoph Scriba, an eminent historian of mathematics, co-edited four volumes of Wallis’s correspondence. Two more volumes were planned, but Scriba died in 2013. He wrote in his introduction to Wallis’s autobiography that other biographies of Wallis tend to contain incongruities that make it hard to take them as entirely objective. Scriba’s example is “the often repeated statement … that Wallis enjoyed ‘such a calm as was not to be ruffled,’” which Scriba claims is not to be found in some of Wallis’s own writings (Scriba, “Autobiography of John Wallis,” 19). Modern historians, who mainly know Wallis through his writings and correspondence, tend to state something to the opposite effect: that he was an unusually contentious man, picking an extraordinary number of scholarly fights with mathematicians at home and abroad; see, e.g., Philip Beeley and Siegmund Probst, “John Wallis (1616–1703): Mathematician and Divine,” in Mathematics and the Divine, ed. Teun Koetsier and Luc Bergmans (Amsterdam: Elsevier, 2005), 443. While it is not easy to know what his actual demeanor was like, there is more to the man’s character than the tone of his correspondence, as there would be with anyone.
  77. Scriba, “Autobiography of John Wallis,” 33, 41.
  78. Ibid., 35.
  79. Ibid., 24.
  80. Ibid., 41.
  81. Ibid., 42.
  82. It is true that there was controversy surrounding the originality of Wallis’s work, and he is certainly concerned with that charge here. Nonetheless, I am interested in the concepts in play and the fact that they may be found flowing from Wallis’s own pen is evidence that he was thinking educationally, in Sommerville’s terms, from an early age.
  83. Sommerville, “Distinction between Indoctrination and Education,”393.
  84. Carruthers, Three Centuries, 3–5. These members were the following, listed with which of the three relevant committees they attended. (This is the full catechism committee before being split into a larger and shorter, and the first and second WSC committees.) Cornelius Burgess (WSC 2), Adoniram Byfield (scribe WSC 2), Richard Byfield (WSC 2), Thomas Case (WSC 2), Daniel Cawdrey (WSC 2), Philip Delmé (Catechism and WSC 1), Stanley Gower (WSC 2), John Greene (WSC 1), Charles Herle (WSC 1), Thomas Hill (Catechism), John Lightfoot (WSC 1), Stephen Marshall (Catechism and WSC 2), Matthew Newcomen (Catechism), Philip Nye (WSC 2), Herbert Palmer (Catechism and WSC 1), William Rayner (WSC 2), Edward Reynolds (Catechism), Samuel Rutherford (WSC 2), Thomas Temple (WSC 1), Anthony Tuckney (Catechism and WSC 2), Richard Vines (WSC 2), and Jason Ward (Catechism and WSC2). Edmund Calamy and Thomas Wilson also did some incidental work on the catechism.
  85. Van Dixhoorn, Minutes and Papers, 1:111–12, citing the Oxford Dictionary of National Biography.
  86. Wallis, Brief and Easie Explanation, A3v–A4r.
  87. Ibid., A4r.
  88. Ibid., A4r–A4v.
  89. Ibid., A4v.
  90. Ibid., 2.
  91. Ibid., 2. This is an expansion on the WSC, and a simplification of the Westminster Confession 2.1 (cf. Philip Schaff, The Creeds of Christendom, 3 vols., 6th ed. [Grand Rapids: Baker, 2007], 2:606). This very issue of God’s infinity was fodder for Wallis’s infamous debate with Thomas Hobbes, who attempted to use Wallis’s views on infinity against him. Hobbes need not have been familiar with the Brief and Easie Explanation, but it was certainly true that the infinite was not just an abstruse concept, irrelevant to orthodoxy. On the contrary, Wallis explicitly claimed he was undermining Hobbes’s mathematical reputation for religious reasons, and Hobbes, at one point in their extended debate, attempted to charge Wallis with holding a position leading to the conclusion that God had a beginning. For a detailed summary, see Beeley and Probst, “John Wallis: Mathematician and Divine,” 445–49.
  92. Wallis, Brief and Easie Explanation, 1–2.
  93. Ibid., 8. The exposition of question 50 is similar.
  94. Ibid., 16.
  95. Ibid., 8–9.
  96. Ibid., 11.
  97. Ibid., 12.
  98. Ibid., 35.
  99. Ibid., 36.
  100. Van Dixhoorn, Minutes and Papers, 4.346.
  101. This session is not in Wallis’s hand, but as we have seen, this doesn’t mean he was unaware of its contents.
  102. Schaff, Creeds of Christendom, 2:764.
  103. Sommerville, “Distinction between Indoctrination and Education,” 391–92.
  104. Green, Christian’s ABC, 262.
  105. Sommerville, “Distinction between Indoctrination and Education,” 392.